Sunday, April 29, 2012

A Personal Note: The First 24 Hours: So Much More, So Much Less

It's Saturday night. We've been back in RI for two days, but the first 24 hours were both much more and much less than we'd hoped for. First, we missed our flight out of Ft. Myers. Half an hour to get to the airport, okay. Ten minutes in the check-in line, okay. Fifty-five minutes in the security line? Oh, no. They closed the doors three minutes before take-off time, and pushed away a minute early. The supervisor and desk folk actually did a high-five at their efficiency as eight of us ran to the gate just as they closed the door. Sorry, they said with such self-satisfaction, but you should have been here two hours early. They were right, of course; it's all about on-time departures.

But they did get us on later flights, and I'm grateful for that. We arrived in RI about 11:30 pm, the house was found half-empty (of course it was; we shipped stuff to FL), and the specter-threat of the break-in was palpable as we tried to find our way to sleep about 1:30 pm. We got some sleep; but about 8 am, there was a thunderous sound that awakened us, the earth and our house shook--almost as if a vehicle had run into our house. But it was only a large tree in our front yard that fell toward and over the street, but in the process taking the power and other lines with it--oh, and the force of it snapping off a telephone pole, the top of which crashed to the road with transformer attached, and all the hazmat-type stuff flowing out in the street. By evening all would be replaced and power restored--but still no phone, TV or internet. All that would be restored today, Saturday.

About 11:30 am of that first morning, about 24 hours after it was clear to us we just might miss that flight, our broker came to visit because she thought bad news should be conveyed in person. Old school. Well, it turns out that our contracted buyer had a problem, and the closing date was no longer on the calendar. He had been fired that morning. He had left his job in Texas to bring his family East for a better opportunity--he thought--had found the house he wanted for his family (ours), only to be fired a couple months or so after selling his Texas house and moving here. If we were disappointed to have the sale of our RI house pushed off into the future yet again, we can only speculate about the pain and despondency visited upon the prospective buyer for whom our house was a part of an exciting next phase of their family life now dissipated, terminated, denied, like the hopes of so many people in recent years. We mourn and pray for their situation.

Later that same day, I visited my elderly parents, 93 and 89. My mother is now in an Alzheimers unit of the same assisted-living facility where my father remains in the assisited-living suite they'd shared. Both were in much worse physical condition than I expected; both were on God's time and at His door. It was a terribly sad and unwelcome experience. They will pass on soon, whether a matter of days, weeks, or a month or two, and I am relieve to have 45 Downing Street as my strong fortress right now, my emotional base from which to work through this difficult passage. The sale of the house can wait a while; I'm pleased to have the additonal time here, especially at this time.

But, as an old friend used to assure me, this too will pass. Life will have its way--we will say our goodbyes, we will sell the house, we will spend time with older friends here, then we will return to our new house, friends and life in Naples. Life goes on.

I hope to see all those friends somewhere in this process. Thanks for being there, and being who you are to us.

Saturday, April 21, 2012

It Depends On What You Mean By "Free Will"--And What You Do With It

[Warning: Another lengthy treatment of an elusive reality. Fair treatment denies brevity, I say. But there is also the matter of how much appetite and patience you have for such topics.]

From the Chronicle Review (of the Chronicle of Higher Education):
Free will has long been a fraught concept among philosophers and theologians. Now neuroscience is entering the fray. 
For centuries, the idea that we are the authors of our own actions, beliefs, and desires has remained central to our sense of self. We choose whom to love, what thoughts to think, which impulses to resist. Or do we? 
Neuroscience suggests something else. We are biochemical puppets, swayed by forces beyond our conscious control. So says Sam Harris, author of the new book, Free Will (Simon & Schuster), a broadside against the notion that we are in control of our own thoughts and actions. Harris's polemic arrives on the heels of Michael S. Gazzaniga's Who's In Charge? Free Will and the Science of the Brain (HarperCollins), and David Eagleman's Incognito: The Secret Lives of the Brain (Pantheon), both provocative forays into a debate that has in recent months spilled out onto op-ed and magazine pages, and countless blogs. 
What's at stake? Just about everything: morality, law, religion, our understanding of accountability and personal accomplishment, even what it means to be human. Harris predicts that a declaration by the scientific community that free will is an illusion would set off "a culture war far more belligerent than the one that has been waged on the subject of evolution." 
--"Is Free Will an Illusion?" The Chronicle Review (3.18.12)
And don't forget the folks most recently studying the genome (which prescribes those neurological, biochemical processes), or the classical and operant conditioning folks, the last-generation students of learning, behavior and acculturation. All have had their reasons and their proofs why so many of our behaviors, including thinking, preferences and choices, are a function of genetic prescriptions or predispositions, or what in one way or another is conditioned or learned in our cultural, social environment. As individuals and as communities, can we work at all well with the notion that an array of deterministic forces render us more complex, but self-deceiving automatons than crafters and directors of our own destiny?

Let's take a look at some excerpts from those recent articles, and try to sort out what neuroscience now adds to this dialogue--and what remains of notions or experience of freedom of thought, choice and behavior. Or does it all depend on what we mean by "free will," the nature, context and focus of the inquiry, the purposes and designs for its conclusions and applications? Of course, I have some thoughts on the subject which I will offer at the end.

First, from Jerry A. Coyne, a professor in the department of ecology and evolution at the University of Chicago:
The term "free will" has so many diverse connotations that I'm obliged to define it before I explain why we don't have it. I construe free will the way I think most people do: At the moment when you have to decide among alternatives, you have free will if you could have chosen otherwise. To put it more technically, if you could rerun the tape of your life up to the moment you make a choice, with every aspect of the universe configured identically, free will means that your choice could have been different. [But there are other meaningful conceptual understandings and definitions of "free will." GH] 
Although we can't really rerun that tape, this sort of free will is ruled out, simply and decisively, by the laws of physics. Your brain and body, the vehicles that make "choices," are composed of molecules, and the arrangement of those molecules is entirely determined by your genes and your environment. Your decisions result from molecular-based electrical impulses and chemical substances transmitted from one brain cell to another. These molecules must obey the laws of physics, so the outputs of our brain—our "choices"—are dictated by those laws. (It's possible, though improbable, that the indeterminacy of quantum physics may tweak behavior a bit, but such random effects can't be part of free will.) And deliberating about your choices in advance doesn't help matters, for that deliberation also reflects brain activity that must obey physical laws. 
To assert that we can freely choose among alternatives is to claim, then, that we can somehow step outside the physical structure of our brain and change its workings. That is impossible. Like the output of a programmed computer, only one choice is ever physically possible: the one you made. As such, the burden of proof rests on those who argue that we can make alternative choices, for that's a claim that our brains, unique among all forms of matter, are exempt from the laws of physics by a spooky, nonphysical "will" that can redirect our own molecules. 
[...] Recent experiments in cognitive science show that some deliberate acts occur before they reach our consciousness (typing or driving, for example), while in other cases, brain scans can predict our choices several seconds before we're conscious of having made them. [Some behavior scientists would cite their own research proofs that many such phenomena are a function of classical (Pavlovian) or operant conditioning triggered by conditioned discriminative stimuli--which, of course,  is just another deterministic process and force. GH] 
[...] So what are the consequences of realizing that physical determinism negates our ability to choose freely? Well, nihilism is not an option: We humans are so constituted, through evolution or otherwise, to believe that we can choose. What is seriously affected is our idea of moral responsibility, which should be discarded along with the idea of free will. If whether we act well or badly is predetermined rather than a real choice, then there is no moral responsibility—only actions that hurt or help others. That realization shouldn't seriously change the way we punish or reward people, because we still need to protect society from criminals, and observing punishment or reward can alter the brains of others, acting as a deterrent or stimulus. [This is what some behaviorists have called "vicarious learning," a demonstrable phenomenon which also implies that as behaviors can be learned or conditioned, they can also be changed or extinguished, even by just observing the context, conditions and results of a situation. Of course, this is no revelation; we've all observed it, even experienced it. GH] What we should discard is the idea of punishment as retribution, which rests on the false notion that people can choose to do wrong. 
The absence of real choice also has implications for religion. Many sects of Christianity, for example, grant salvation only to those who freely choose Jesus as their savior. [There is very much in question the concept embraced here, what is meant by any particular Christian or Christian tradition when referring to "free will." There are differences and ambiguities. And then there are the many confusing, antithetical, yet authoritative Biblical references to a more deterministic, "predestined" path of faith for the "elect" among professing believers--whether from various Calvinist understandings and supporting Scriptures found often in Paul's Epistles, or other sources like Psalm 139. GH] 
And some theologians explain human evil as an unavoidable byproduct of God's gift of free will. If free will goes, so do those beliefs. But of course religion won't relinquish those ideas, for such important dogma is immune to scientific advances. [Yes, and it is also likely immune because of the ambiguities in Scripture and teaching I last referenced, and the insulating mystery in the faith understanding that God's ways and understandings are not our ways and understanding. GH] 
[...] Although science strongly suggests that free will of the sort I defined doesn't exist, this view is unpopular because it contradicts our powerful feeling that we make real choices. In response, some philosophers—most of them determinists who agree with me that our decisions are preordained—have redefined free will in ways that allow us to have it. I see most of these definitions as face-saving devices designed to prop up our feeling of autonomy...  
---"You Don't Have Free Will," by Jerry A Coyne, The Chronicle Review (3.19.12) 
That's one clear, direct point of view, even if it does not deal with the alternative arguments or views sufficiently. Next is Alfred R. Mele, a professor of philosophy at Florida State University. He is the director of Big Questions in Free Will, an investigation of the science, philosophy, and theology of free will, supported by a $4.4-million grant from the John Templeton Foundation.
Is free will an illusion? Recent scientific arguments for an affirmative answer have a simple structure. First, data are offered in support of some striking empirical proposition—for example, that conscious intentions never play any role in producing corresponding actions. Then this proposition is linked to a statement about what free will means to yield the conclusion that it does not exist. [As in the first essay. GH] 
In my book Effective Intentions: The Power of Conscious Will (Oxford University Press, 2009), I explain why the data do not justify such arguments. Sometimes I am told that even if I am correct, I overlook the best scientific argument for the nonexistence of free will. This claim, in a nutshell, has two parts: Free will depends on the activity of nonphysical minds or souls, and scientists have shown that something physical—the brain—is doing all the work. 
As the majority of philosophers understand the concept, free will doesn't depend at all on the existence of nonphysical minds or souls. But philosophers don't own this expression. If anyone owns it, people in general do. So I conducted some simple studies. 
In one, I invited participants to imagine a scenario in which scientists had proved that everything in the universe is physical and that what we refer to as a "mind" is actually a brain at work. In this scenario, a man sees a $20 bill fall from a stranger's pocket, considers returning it, and decides to keep it. Asked whether he had free will when he made that decision, 73 percent answer yes. This study suggests that a majority of people do not see having a nonphysical mind or soul as a requirement for free will. [Is that satisfactorily proved by this study uncontrolled for whether the participants have fully accepted and internalized the notion that brain equals mind completely? GH] 
If free will does not depend on souls, what is the scientific evidence that it is an illusion? I'll briefly discuss just one study. Chun Siong Soon and colleagues, in a 2008 Nature Neuroscience article, report the results of an experiment in which participants were asked to make simple decisions while their brain activity was measured using functional magnetic resonance imaging, or fMRI. The options were always two buttons, and nothing hinged on which was pressed. Soon and coauthors write: "We found that two brain regions encoded with high accuracy whether the subject was about to choose the left or right response prior to the conscious decision," noting that "the predictive neural information preceded the conscious motor decision by up to 10 seconds." The science writer Elsa Youngsteadt represented these results as suggesting that "the unconscious brain calls the shots, making free will an illusory afterthought." 
In this study, however, the predictions are accurate only 60 percent of the time. Using a coin, I can predict with 50-percent accuracy which button a participant will press next. And if the person agrees not to press a button for a minute (or an hour), I can make my predictions a minute (or an hour) in advance. I come out 10 points worse in accuracy, but I win big in terms of time. 
So what is indicated by the neural activity that Soon and colleagues measured? My money is on a slight unconscious bias toward a particular button—a bias that may give the participant about a 60-percent chance of pressing that button next.
Given such flimsy evidence, I do not recommend betting the farm on the nonexistence of free will. 
---"The Case Against the Case Against Free Will," by Alfred R/ Mele, The Chronicle Review (3.18.12)
There appears more than enough flimsy evidence to go around in that point of view. Next up is Michael S. Gazzaniga, director of the SAGE Center for the Study of the Mind at the University of California at Santa Barbara. He is the author, most recently, of Who's In Charge? Free Will and the Science of the Brain (HarperCollins, 2011).
The exquisite machine that generates our mental life also lives in a social world and develops rules for living within a social network. For the social network to function, each person assigns each other person responsibility for his or her actions. There are rules for traffic that exist and are only understood and adopted when cars interact. It is the same for human interactions. Just as we would not try to understand traffic by studying the mechanics of cars, we should not try to understand brains to understand the idea of responsibility. Responsibility exists at a different level of organization: the social level, not in our determined brains. 
Viewing the age-old question of free will in this framework has many implications. Holding people responsible for their actions remains untouched and intact since that is a value granted by society. We all learn and obey rules, both personal and social. Following social rules, as they say, is part of our DNA. Virtually every human can follow rules no matter what mental state he or she is in. 
[...] We should hold people responsible for their actions. No excuses. That keeps everything simple and clean. Once accountability is established, we can then take up the more challenging questions of what as a society we should do about someone engaged in wrongdoing. We can debate punishment, treatment, isolation, or many other ways to enforce accountability in a social network. Those are truly difficult issues. Establishing how to think about responsibility is not. 
---"Free Will is an Illusion, but You're Still Responsible for Your Actions," by Michael S. Gazzaniga, The Chronicle Review (3.18.12)
Okay, that one was more about the notion of personal responsibility assuming the neuroscientist are right than the reasons why they are; but a conversation worth having. Next is Hilary Bok, an associate professor of philosophy at the Johns Hopkins University. She is the author of Freedom and Responsibility (Princeton University Press, 1998).
Whether this view provides an adequate account of free will is not a problem neuroscience can solve. Neuroscience can explain what happens in our brains: how we perceive and think, how we weigh conflicting considerations and make choices, and so forth. But the question of whether freedom and moral responsibility are compatible with free will is not a scientific one, and we should not expect scientists to answer it. [Ah, but that very statement is very much at the heart of the different understandings of the questions, context, methodologies, purposes and implications. GH] 
Whatever their views on the compatibility of freedom and determinism, most philosophers agree that someone can be free only if she can make a reasoned choice among various alternatives, and act on her decision; in short, only if she has the capacity for self-government. 
Neuroscience can help us to understand what this capacity is and how it can be strengthened. What, for instance, determines when we engage in conscious self-regulation, and how might we ensure that we do so when we need to? If the exercise of self-government can deplete our capacity for further self-government in the short run, what exactly is depleted, and how might we compensate for its loss? Does self-government deplete our resources in the short run while strengthening them over time, like physical exercise, or does it simply weaken our ability to govern ourselves without any compensating benefit? 
Neuroscience can answer those questions, and it can provide causal explanations of human action, but it can't resolve the question of whether or not such explanations are compatible with free will. 
---"Want to Understand Free Will? Don't Look to Neuroscience," by Hilary Bok, The Chronicle Review (3.18.12)
Not bad; not adequately responsive to the points of the scientists, but relevant and worthy considerations. Not bad. Next, Owen D. Jones, a professor of law and biological sciences at Vanderbilt University. His book Law and Neuroscience, with Jeffrey Schall and Francis Shen, is forthcoming from Aspen Publishers next year.
Well, his frustration with the overworked and redundant arguments in the discussion quickly give way to furthering the arguments in the discussion--and advance the discussion very well he does. Now last, the estimable and entertaining Paul Bloom, a professor of psychology and cognitive science at Yale University. His next book, Just Babies: The Origins of Good and Evil, will be published next year by Crown.
I and my views find more compatibility and comfort with Mr. Bloom and his take on it all. But, as threatened, I reserve the last word for myself. Since a good friend finds it irksome when I use pullquotes from something I've written before, here I will just share with you some long-held views, although you will find very similar ideas and language, but more of it, in two pieces called "Choices"  and "The Limits of Merit & Choice" written by someone or other some years ago.

Your freedom and choices, it appears, may be more limited than you think. What remains to you is the constant drumbeat of scholarly research that informs us we are each bound in our own Procrustean bed, genetically-defined, fixed more-or-less, and further limited by the environments we were reared in and live in.

That unwelcome, deterministic reality is an earnest finger poked in our chest, demanding to be heard, attesting repeatedly to the inherited and conditioned responses and qualities that characterize what we do, what we think, who we are. A more euphemistic sentiment might allude to the limits and conditions on the freedom of man. A more direct and fatalistic disposition might charge that what the genes don't dictate, the environment will. And if the genetic brand of determinism is incomprehensible or unacceptable to you, don't expect to find more comfort in the world of conditioned behavior and beliefs. Or do you believe that the realities of family and cultural conditioning are any less powerful than your genetic endowment?

So do not deceive yourself or be deceived. The power of our genetic endowment and the behavioral conditioning of our environment are great indeed. With compelling research in hand, science would reasonably advise you that your very personality and many of your personal traits and predilections are influenced significantly by your genes. So is your predisposition to pursue certain types of vocations or interests, or fall prey to certain illnesses or diseases. And the ubiquitous power of the environment, the impact of family and culture as explained by the learning and conditioning sciences, has been well understood much longer.

Of course, many are simply in denial. They would wish it all away, dismiss it as exaggerated in impact and import. But that's a fool's errand, whether born of intellectual ignorance, emotional defensiveness, or worse, a stiff-necked, misguided mission to carry water for various ideological, religious or social agendas. They greatly underestimate the near uncontrollable, deterministic power of genetic inheritance and environmental conditioning. But operating under a self-constructed illusion of freedom—denying, distorting or reshaping the truth—has never been the right answer, or even a workable answer. Then you are working with a lie, and have no chance at all.

You might well conclude, then, that the natural condition of man is an utter lack of freedom, the absence of real, voluntary personal choices—or, put another way, that any sense of freedom exists only in ignorance.

Moving Toward a Reality of Freedom

If all this is just too emotionally confining and personally limiting, too threatening to your notion of freedom and identity, potential and possibilities—it should be. Oh, it's not that this is all bad science, a cruel, controlling hoax, a lie. No, in large part it is too true. And the only real uncertainty is how large a part each factor plays in influencing the understanding of our alternatives and the making of our choices. But it isn't as bleak as it sounds.

In a real sense, you can enjoy and exercise more real freedom. Your freedom is first in knowing what has made you who you are, the way you are—and how. You can better understand your genetic predispositions and prescriptions; more is being learned about such things every day, and you can have your genetic endowment examined and explained to you for a reasonable price at commercial providers of such services.

It is also in knowing how your family and cultural environment has shaped you, conditioned you, to be who you are, the way you are. You can learn more about such processes, which makes alternatives more real--the potential effect on you of different places and people, different thinking and ways of doing things. Your freedom is in that knowledge. You can also read what different people are reading, listen for what they are saying, watch for what they are doing. In this way you can learn more about what you need to know, and better understand.

You can, then, see yourself and others in a different, more interdependent way, a more understanding and sympathetic way. And to the extent you know the ways you and others are a product of your changeable circumstances—family, culture, your time and place, the box you are in—you have a blueprint for personal change.

You can have real alternatives and choices to make. And you can have better-informed reasons to believe in and make your choices. If there is anything more to your notion of freedom than a hollow log, you can know that there are better choices you can make, actions you can take, to access better opportunities to grow—or not.

And the scope of the alternatives you entertain and understand, and the particular choices you pursue with understanding, also define your freedom, don't they? A choice to refrain from expanding your experience, knowledge or ability is, in effect, a choice to limit or deny your future choices—and therefore the future scope of your freedom. So it is also with choices to indulge foolish, anti-social or base desires and emotions. They can threaten life or health, result in imprisonment or legal limitations, or compromise your honor, trustworthiness, or self-esteem in ways that limit your future relationships and opportunities. These acts, too, limit your future choices and freedom. And they can be better controlled.

So, you can plan your way toward readiness to take the first steps out of the behavioral box you're in. You can plan your way to choosing better alternatives and expand your possibilities, that they are real and waiting for you—even calling you.

Move, literally. Change the physical place you are in and the people around you. Seek people and situations that will expect more of what you want to expect of yourself. They can notably change your actions, what you do, change your thinking, and to some extent, who you are. And the more you know about yourself—about those influencing factors—the more readily, competently you will make choices for effective change in your life. And yes, that honest knowledge will also have to acknowledge your limitations as well as your potential. That's important, too. But, most often, there will be some better alternatives, some better choices.

Please make some choices that work for other people, too—people you probably don't know or don't know well. To one extent or another, you share with them some of the same space, even if not the same experiential boxes. Make some choices for tolerance or, better still, acceptance and civility. Or, go crazy: think about respect and caring and serving.

Make some choices for community and your best contribution to it. Consider more charitably the poor, the immigrant, the stranger, the prisoner. Consider again issues of access to education and health care, and stewardship of our environment. Be part of solutions, not problems; building up, not tearing down; caring, not neglecting or, worse still, hating. You can do this. But you need to embrace a new sense of responsibility, some knowledge of the alternatives and possibilities—your possibilities. And you have to make some choices.

The Limits of Merit & Choice

Now, let's take a look at another application in the broad arena of social policy that begs for understanding of these deterministic forces in the lives of individuals and groups of people. It's about how ignorance about such things, or unwillingness to understand, leads us embrace social half-truths that harm us more than help us, both as individuals and as a society.

It's not a fabrication, a lie. It's just not the whole truth. And the part that's been omitted—or is it just ignored?—should provide the basis for us to consider providing better for those most in need. I'm speaking of our unwarranted overemphasis on personal merit and, as we've discussed elsewhere, freedom of choice.

It really does appeal to us, all of us. It panders to our self-esteem, our sense of self-determination and self-sufficiency, our self-congratulatory tendencies. We want to believe that we earned what we have—that we pulled ourselves up by our bootstraps, mapped out our plans, prepared ourselves, then worked hard, harder than the next guy, earning our way to our definition of success. And in a very real, experiential sense, it is true. (Most of us feel that's exactly what we've done!)

We also want to believe that it's not our fault if the next guy wasn't as ambitious, didn't prepare himself as well, didn't work as hard, wasn't as able. It's not our fault if he was too lazy or irresponsible, lacked discipline, character or interpersonal capability. It's not our fault if he wasn't intelligent, talented or savvy enough. It's not our fault if he was too different, unstable or disabled. We each get what we earn, what we deserve. (Isn't that right?)

And what of the poor, the competitive failures of whatever stripe? Why, they just suffer the natural consequences of their own failings and failure. And that's not our fault, either. How could it be? (So, why should it be our responsibility?)

Of course it's not your fault or mine—at least not most of the time. But most often, neither is it theirs. Notably, in a most real sense, most often we are no more the author of our successes than they are of their failures. Heresy, indeed! But let me briefly explain why, in more empirical terms, this is also true.

You understand the continuing discussion and research about nature and nurture, of course. We discussed it in Choices. You're familiar with the debate about how much of the way we are is the result of the genetic legacy of our parents and forbears, and how much is the result of the way we are conditioned and schooled, what we learn in our families, communities and cultures. What is not in doubt is that the combination of our genes, family, culture and education determines who we are, how we act, and the likely limits of our potential and achievements. And if most everyone still has some alternatives, some choices, those afforded the least able of our brethren, the least fortunate, are so many fewer and so much narrower, and their ability to act on them is so much less. 

The irony is that we discuss it, make casual affirming observations about it in everyday life, even ponder it with personal satisfaction or dismay, but then go about our lives dealing with each other, making personal and organizational decisions and crafting public policy as though we didn't know it or didn't believe it. The truth is that the power and perceived importance of our public, cultural half-myths trump what we instinctively know and what science more resoundingly than ever confirms. The truth is inconvenient and unwelcome to our sense of independence, accomplishment and self worth. It can coexist only uncomfortably with those cultural values.

So, just how right, how defensible, then, is that laissez-faire foundation on which we stand? How fair or egalitarian, how ethical and moral, how humane and intelligent are our assumptions about getting what we earn or deserve? How even is the playing field, how just the result? Is it not true that there, but for the deal of the genetic cards, the spin of the birth-place roulette, go I—dross in the crucible of our competitive society, failed or failing, and much in need of the help and support of my community, my more fortunate brethren? Shouldn't the integrity of an accountable, civilized society demand a full understanding and honest acknowledgment of this reality? Wouldn't it respond honestly, responsibly, and effectively to the needs of the innocent poor, infirm and unable? Wouldn't health care, education, and subsistence living be their right as it would everyone's?

(My Christian faith informs me that we are each just who God intended us to be based on the dictates of our singular spiritual paths, and the genetic endowment and life circumstances that deliver us there. And more, we have responsibilities and accountabilities for one another. That is the signal characteristic of faith community, and any real community. No one left behind.) 

Friday, April 20, 2012

Who Pays What Taxes: 11 Charts - The Atlantic

The Atlantic on-line offers an illuminating article and set of charts that set straight the facts about who or what groups pay how much of what kinds of taxes, and how that differs from other groups. It will take a little attention and effort, but it will help clear up some of the disinformation and outright lies that keep being promoted by the various political and financial interests. It's worth the read.



Link:
How We Pay Taxes: 11 Charts

Eight questions you've always wanted to ask about U.S. taxes, answered with pictures!
  

Tuesday, April 10, 2012

A West Wing Bible Lesson



The West Wing character Jed Bartlett is a professing Roman Catholic Christian, as well as President of the United States. Here, a passionate, indignant President Bartlett makes his point so well, and with rhetorical flair: to be a Christian doesn't mean we are to be members of what he indelicately, pejoratively refers to as the "ignorant, tight-ass club."  Legalism, discrimination and judgment are not the paths we're called to walk.

To the contrary, we are called to be well-informed, thoughtful and generous people whose beliefs and behavior reflect first the love, compassion and humility of Christ. And we are to be nonjudgmental and forgiving of others, too. Lofty standards often unmet, they are nonetheless at the heart of our faith understandings and aspirations.

We are also to understand the differences--in historical and cultural context, and their relevance today--between the Bible's early accounts of the ancient people Israel and some of the harsher elements of the Mosaic Covenant (the Law), and the New Testament's accounts and teaching of the New Covenant of Love in Christ. And we might venture a nod of acknowledgment, even acceptance, of the understandings of an advancing, affirming humanism, particularly in the more modern socio-political context of the West.

Loved West Wing and President Bartlett, and in this clip his character and understanding show as clearly as his passion and rhetorical giftedness.

Monday, April 9, 2012

Easter

Easter. A day, an experience, of renewal, hope and gratitude. God willing.


Saturday, April 7, 2012

Cosmology: An Expanding, Flat Universe and the Search for Reasons Why

Time to look over the cutting edge of what's happening in physics. To the surprise of many physicists and onlookers, the most recent generation of research reveals the universe is not only expanding, but doing so at an increasing rate. More--and notwithstanding the curved-space implications of Einstein's general theory of relativity--the universe is flat. Now, the next generation of research is trying to explain why this is so. Critical to the explanation is the amount and nature of dark energy--and whether the relationshop between dark energy's negative pressure and its positive energy density proves a cosmological constant of -1. Challenging stuff, but fascinating.

In February, The Economist offered a remarkably good and readable survey of the state of affairs in this area of physics research. From that article:
It has been known since the late 1920s that the universe is getting bigger. But it was thought that the expansion was slowing. When in 1998 two independent studies reached the opposite conclusion, cosmology was knocked head over heels. Since then, 5,000 papers have been written to try to explain (or explain away) this result. "That's more than one a day," marvels Saul Perlmutter, of the Lawrence Berkeley National Laboratory, who led the Supernova Cosmology Project—one of the studies that was responsible for dropping the bombshell. Last October that work earned Dr Perlmutter the Nobel prize for physics, which he shared with Brian Schmidt and Adam Riess, who led the other study, the High-Z Supernova Search. 
---"Cosmology: The dark side of the universe," The Economist, Science and Technology (2.18.12)
But what does that have to do with the flatness of the universe and the hard to reconcile curved-space phenomenon resulting from Einstein's general theory of relativity? More from The Economist:
Many of those 5,000 papers deal with something that has come to be known as dark energy. One reason for its popularity is that, at one fell swoop, it explains another big cosmological find of recent years. In the early 1990s studies of the cosmic microwave background (CMB), an all-pervading sea of microwaves which reveals what the universe looked like when it was just 380,000 years old, showed that the universe, then and now, was "flat". However big a triangle you draw on it—the corners could be billions of light years apart—the angles in it would add up to 180°, just as they do in a school exercise book. 
That might not surprise people whose geometrical endeavours have never gone beyond such books. But it surprised many physicists. At some scales space is not at all flat: the power of Albert Einstein's theory of general relativity lies in its interpretation of gravity in terms of curved space. Cosmologists were quite prepared for it to be curved at the grandest of scales, and intrigued to discover that it was not.
So far so good, but where does the amount and nature of dark energy come into play, and why does the relationship of its postive and negative qualities have to prove a cosmological or universal constant?
Relativity says that for the universe to be flat, it has to have a very particular density—which in relativity is a measure not just of the mass contained in a certain volume, but also of the energy. The puzzle was that various lines of evidence showed that the universe's endowment of ordinary matter (the stuff that people, planets and stars are made of) would give it just 4% of that density. Adding in extraordinary matter—"dark matter", not made of atoms, that interacts with the rest of the universe almost only by means of gravity—gets at most an extra 22%. That left almost three-quarters of the critical density unaccounted for. Theorists such as Michael Turner, of the University of Chicago, became convinced that there was something big missing from their picture of the universe. 
Whatever it is that is driving the universe's accelerating expansion fits the bill rather well. Add the amount of energy needed to keep cosmic acceleration going to the amount of matter and energy in the universe already accounted for and you have more or less exactly the density of matter and energy needed to make the universe flat. But there is a catch; for the sums to tally, that "dark energy"—Dr Turner is thought to have coined the term— must be very strange stuff indeed. According to Einstein's theory of relativity, energy in the form of radiation has the same sort of gravitational effect as matter does—the photons of which light is made exert a pressure, and this in turn gives rise to a gravitational attraction. In order to drive its acceleration, then, dark energy must instead have a repulsive effect. It must, in other words, exert a negative pressure. 
Divide dark energy's pressure (negative) by its energy density (positive) and you get something cosmologists label "w". It is easy to see that w must be negative. Observations made since 1998 suggest that w is pretty close to -1. If it were found to be exactly -1, that would make dark energy something physicists call a cosmological constant. A cosmological constant is the same no matter where in the universe you look—an inherent, unchanging feature of the fabric of creation, however much it expands, twists or ties itself in knots.
And the cosmological constant also has it's history inextricably bound up in the history of Einstein's general theory of relativity.
The cosmological constant is another thing first dreamed up by Einstein. On realising that the equations of general relativity allowed for the universe's expansion (or, indeed, contraction), he added a parameter describing just such a constant in order to keep it from doing either. For all his notoriously counterintuitive predictions, an expanding universe was one he was not prepared to countenance, at least not in 1917, when he published his theory. After Edwin Hubble's discovery 12 years later that other galaxies were indeed streaming away from Earth's Milky Way backyard, Einstein dropped the tweak. No doubt miffed that he had not trusted his maths in the first place, he later called the cosmological constant his "biggest blunder". 
By then, though, the cosmological constant had been seized upon by quantum theorists [the physicists who focus on the physics of the smallest things, the sub-atomic particles], themselves in the midst of turning physics on its head. Quantum theory says that the seemingly empty vacuum of space is, in fact, not empty at all. Instead it is constantly abuzz with "virtual" particles flitting in and out of existence. The energy resulting from all this buzzing—vacuum energy—should be a fixed feature of space—in other words, a cosmological constant. 
And, in principle, it could also propel the universe's expansion. Thus vacuum energy and dark energy might be the same thing. But this theoretical neatness runs into a practical problem. A naive approach to quantum theory says that vacuum energy should be a whopping 1060 to 10120 times bigger than dark energy's estimated energy density. Some physicists call this "the worst prediction ever". Working out why vacuum energy is not so vast has been a problem for physics ever since.
And that brings us around to those who theorize the answer is connected to "string theory."
Cliff Burgess, from Perimeter Institute for Theoretical Physics in Waterloo, Ontario, and the author of a handful of the 5,000 papers Dr Perlmutter has dug up, thinks he has a solution; the vacuum energy is vast, but it is almost all hidden away in extra spatial dimensions. Unlike the familiar three of length, breadth and height, these extra dimensions are curled up so tightly that they elude detection (though scientists are trying to prise them open in particle accelerators like the Large Hadron Collider near Geneva). Extra dimensions are of interest because string theory, a class of mathematical models based on quantum theory that seeks to describe reality in the most fundamental way, requires that there be at least six of them, maybe more. 
What makes Dr Burgess's proposal unusual is that he went out on a limb and suggested that these energy-sapping, curled-up extra dimensions should be as big as a few microns across, gargantuan by string-theory standards. The reason they have not been noticed by chipmakers, virologists and others who pay attention to things on the micron scale, he contends, is that, like dark matter, they are sensitive only to gravity, and relatively oblivious to the other three of nature's fundamental interactions: electromagnetism and the weak and strong nuclear forces. This may sound like a cheap excuse but it makes robust mathematical sense. And it makes predictions; at micron scales the attraction between two masses will no longer depend on the square of the distance between them in the way that physicists since Newton have required it to. 
[...] If Dr Burgess is right, vacuum energy and dark energy are the same thing, a cosmological constant, and w is exactly equal to -1. What, though, if it is not? Then dark energy would have to be something that varies in space, time, or both, and is close to -1 today just by coincidence. Names applied to this something else include quintessence, k-essence, phantom energy and a bunch more, depending on which theorist you ask and what properties you think likely. It would be a new fundamental force, one that rears its head only at vast cosmic distances. 
[...]The more precisely w comes to look like -1, the more enthusiasm there will be for cosmological constant theories, which require that value, and the less enthusiasm there will be for fifth forces and modified gravity, part of the charm of which is that they can work with other values. This is where telescopes like Cerro Tololo come in. Existing data from ground-based and space telescopes put w at between -1.1 and -0.9. DES will aim to narrow the margin of uncertainty down to just 0.01. To do so, it will take 400 one-gigabyte snaps a night for 525 nights over five years (the remaining telescope time will be split between other science projects). And it will use an array of clever techniques to analyse the data.
But there's an overarching  problem, possibly an insuperable one, in proving the cosmological constant inherent in the positive and negative qualities of dark energy--at least at this time. The article concludes:
The rub is that no amount of observations can ever pin down the figure for w with perfect accuracy. That would require infinite precision, something impossible to achieve even in an ever-expanding universe. And the whole constant idea falls to pieces if w is even a smidgen off -1. 
More than any other scientific problem the cosmic-expansion conundrum presents scientists with an existential quandary. "It could be a 22nd-century problem we stumbled upon in the 20th century," says Dr Turner. Some researchers may begin to feel time would be better spent on other scientific pursuits. 
Many astronomers, including Dr Perlmutter, are quietly hoping that as DES and the host of other acronyms come online, they will spring another surprise, like the one that first propelled cosmic acceleration into the limelight in 1998. Whether they do or not, though, dark energy—or whatever else is causing the universe to speed up—is probably too big a conundrum for one generation to crack. It will cause boffins to rack their brains for years to come.
There is much more shared in this article:  the details of the more recent research, formulation of next questions and next steps in the research, and the projects and research methodologies organized to address them. It is fully worth your time to read it all.

Link to article:

Has Europe [and the U.S.] lost its soul?--Rabbi Jonathan Sachs

I send this essay/speech by Rabbi Sachs along to a range of people with whom I feel it is important to share it--either because it addresses common Judeo-Christian faith values and understandings, or because it provides understanding of why and how my faith as well as my humanism informs my economic, political and social values and my sense of social responsibility. Rabbi Sachs is thoughtful, insightful and authoritative in his reflections and admonitions. I share fully his understandings and views. I hope you find them informative and worthy, if not affirming of your own.

Please read it. To do so, just click here.

*          *          *          *          *

This piece was sent to me by old friend, David Greenhalgh, professor of education and director of the Ph.D program in organizational development at Eastern University, a Christian university in Eastern Pennsylvania. Thank you, David.

Jonathan Sacks has been Chief Rabbi of the United Hebrew Congregations of the Commonwealth since September 1991. Educated at Gonville and Caius College, Cambridge, where he obtained first class honours in Philosophy, Jonathan Sacks pursued postgraduate studies at New College, Oxford, and King's College London, gaining his PH. D in 1981 and rabbinic ordination from Jews' College and Yeshiva Etz Chaim. The Chief Rabbi has been a visiting professor at several universities in Britain, the United States and Israel, and is currently Visiting Professor of Theology at Kings' College London. He holds many honorary degrees, including a Doctor of Divinity conferred to mark his first ten years in office, by the Archbishop of Canterbury.

The Chief Rabbi received the Jerusalem Prize 1995 for his contribution to diaspora Jewish life, and was knighted by Her Majesty The Queen in 2005. He was made a Life Peer and took his seat in the House of Lords on 27th October 2009, where he sits on the cross benches as Baron Sacks of Aldgate in the City of London.

Many of his books have been translated into French, Italian, Dutch, German, Portuguese, Korean and Hebrew. Those of his titles currently in print in English, include: The Great Partnership: God, Science and the Search for Meaning, The Persistence of Faith, Dignity of Difference: How to Avoid the Clash of Civilizations, Covenant and Conversation: Exodus, Covenant and Conversation: Genesis, Future Tense, and From Optimism to Hope.